Mathematics Prelims

February 24, 2009

Concrete and Non-Concrete Categories (Informally)

Filed under: Category Theory — cjohnson @ 4:01 pm

The categories that naturally come to mind when trying to think up examples of a category (such as sets with functions, groups with homomorphisms, topological spaces with continuous maps, …) are sometimes called concrete categories.  These are categories where the objects are sets, usually with some additional structure (group structure, a topology, etc.), and the morphisms are well-defined functions between those sets that preserve the structure.  For example, consider Top, the category of topological spaces with continuous maps.

In the case of Top it’s easy to check that the identity map is continuous, that composition of continuous functions yields another continuous function, and function composition in general is associative.  With a continuous map, say f : S \to T, we’re taking a point s \in S and assigning it to a single point f(s) \in T (so we have a well-defined function between two sets) in such a way that if we have an open subset U \subseteq T and look at the preimage of each point in U, we get an open set in f^{-1}(U) \subseteq S.  It is in this sense that the structure of the topological space is preserved: preimages of open sets are open sets.  In the case of Grp, our morphisms are group homomorphisms, which by their very definition respect the group structure.

There are, of course, categories which are not concrete.  In the last post we saw a very simple category with three objects.  These objects aren’t sets, they’re just “things” that we decided to label A, B, and C.  The morphisms between these objects aren’t functions in any sense of the word: they don’t associate inputs with outputs, there aren’t even any “inputs” or “outputs” to speak of!  Our morphisms are literally just arrows that start at one object and end at another.  (For this reason some people simply refer to the morphisms of a category as arrows.)

The category $latex \mathcal{C}$

The above is about as far from a concrete category as you can get, but consider the following example from Awodey.  Let the objects of the category be sets.  For any sets A and B a morphism from A to B is any subset of A \times B (that is, any relation on A and B).  The identity relation is taken to be \{(a, a) : a \in A\}.  For composition of two relations, we say that \{(a, c)\} is the composition of \{(a, b)\} and \{(b, c)\} where (a, c) is in the set iff there is a b_0 \in B such that (a, b_0) and (b_0, c) are in the original relations.  Here are objects are sets, but the arrows are not functions.  The morphisms are collections of ordered pairs (a, b) with a \in A and b \in B.  This is not a function as we may “associate” one a \in A with several items in B.  For example, we may have a morphism \{(a, b_1), (a, b_2)\} with b_1 \neq b_2.

Leave a Comment »

No comments yet.

RSS feed for comments on this post. TrackBack URI

Leave a comment

Create a free website or blog at WordPress.com.